New ebooks From Canadian Indies

Political

Showing 17-24 of 28 books
Sort by:
View Mode:
Pessimism of the Intellect, Optimism of the Will

Pessimism of the Intellect, Optimism of the Will

The Political Philosophy of Kai Nielsen
edited by David Rondel & Alex Sager, contributions by Kai Nielsen
edition:eBook
also available: Paperback
tagged : political, religious, ethics & moral philosophy
More Info
Revisioning Europe

Revisioning Europe

The Films of John Berger and Alain Tanner
by Jerry White
edition:eBook
also available: Paperback
tagged : history & criticism, political, western
More Info
Soren Kierkegaard’s Psychology

Soren Kierkegaard’s Psychology

by Med Ib Ostenfeld
edition:eBook
tagged : existentialism, social, political
More Info
Technology and Empire

Technology and Empire

by George Grant, introduction by Andrew Potter
edition:eBook
also available: Paperback Paperback
tagged : political, social aspects
More Info
Technology and Justice

Technology and Justice

by George Grant, introduction by Hugh Donald Forbes
edition:eBook
also available: Paperback Paperback
tagged : political, social aspects
More Info
The End(s) of Community

The End(s) of Community

History, Sovereignty, and the Question of Law
by Joshua Ben David Nichols
edition:eBook
also available: Paperback
tagged : post-structuralism, political, criticism
More Info
Excerpt

Excerpt from The End(s) of Community: History, Sovereignty, and the Question of Law by Joshua Ben David Nichols

From the Introduction

What are the limits of law? At first glance this question seems commonplace. After all there is no law without limitations. In order for law to function, its limits must be either determined or determinable. They are, quite simply, conceptually co-determined. Given this relation, it seems one could simply respond with a basic indicative “here” or “there,” as if responding to a tourist asking for directions. But if we pause and begin to consider this question a little more carefully, it quickly loses its everyday veneer. There is a troubling undercurrent to this question, one that echoes Antigone's animal-like cry, Leontius' irrepressible desire to see, or the ultimate fate of the officer in Kafka's “In the Penal Colony. ”1 This undercurrent shifts the very force and character of the question from the simple, everyday point of reference (i. e. , from the specific legal limits for a given activity to the imaginary lines that define a jurisdiction and the set of qualities that determine the “common” of community) to a radical contestation of the power to make law. As soon as we begin to attune our ear to this undercurrent, the simple response of “here” or “there” suddenly becomes abstract to the point of absurdity. We are drawn towards that which is set outside of the law—the king, the outlaw, and the scaffold—in an attempt to find the stakes of the question itself. However one chooses to answer this question—and we should note that it is one always already being both asked and answered—determines the line that both unites and divides sovereignty and democracy, force and law.

This text addresses the philosophical genealogies of these fundamental concepts in order to respond to the question. In particular it sets out to examine how the tradition of Western philosophy has accounted for the foundations of law, that is, for the movement from a “state of nature” to political order. Traditionally, the character of the “sovereign” or “lawgiver” has provided the solution to this problem. The sovereign sets the limits of the law by presenting its authority as natural or at the very least necessary, but this solution simply suspends or defers the question of the limits of law (i. e. , the line between force and law). Effectively, by proclaiming law, the sovereign faces the problem of responsibility. The solution to this problem has been the claim that the sovereign's relationship to the law is exceptional, that is, it may both found and enforce law, but it is not bound by it. This exceptional status requires an explanatory framework, as without one the claim to the rule of law is impossible to maintain. Quite simply, sovereignty requires a unified historical narrative to contextualize its foundations (i. e. , fate), give meaning to its future (i. e. , messianism), and thereby preserve its authority within the present. This requirement has effectively tied sovereignty to universal history̬or, to borrow Lyotard's terminology,”grand historical narratives”—at the conceptual level.

This line of inquiry is by no means easy. When we begin to question the historical foundations of the relationship between sovereignty and law, we are immediately confronted with a convoluted mixture of jurisprudence and theology. While it is possible to argue that this metaphysical component is merely a distraction, and that the true basis of both sovereignty and the legal order is simply violence, such a hypothesis is fundamentally incomplete. Simply dismissing metaphysics as a façade renders one unable to account for the series of structural effects the foundational myth has within the system.

Myth serves to bind the sovereign and the community together—a classic example being the so-called “noble lie” in the Republic—and thus set the stage for the proclamation of laws that are received as more than a set of externally imposed limits. In the twinkling of an eye, individuals become moral subjects and the rule of the strongest becomes the rule of law. And this is not the end of the story. While any given mythology may serve to found law and convert force into law, it cannot simply be dispensed with once the foundation is in place, for it introduces a set of relationships and rules that must be maintained. Like the script for an elaborate stage play, it defines the scenes and sets the actors in motion.

Nevertheless, when one starts to question the logic of the play itself, it begins to unravel. When we leave the script and pose a simple and direct question, such as “Who are you to proclaim the law?” the sovereign is forced either to make the obvious tautological assertion “I am the King”—a kindness to remind us of our place within the script—or to simply change the scene and have us arrested and executed for high treason. It is violence that both founds and maintains the relationship that binds the play to the script. —And yet, paradoxically, it is acts of violenceand here I draw directly on Benjamin's use of the German term Gewalt—that strain this relationship to the point of unworking it. The magic circle that leads from the subject to the sovereign draws itself towards the limit in and through exercising the right to kill.

close this panel
The Question of Peace in Modern Political Thought

The Question of Peace in Modern Political Thought

edited by Toivo Koivukoski & David Edward Tabachnick
edition:eBook
also available: Paperback
tagged : peace, security (national & international), political
More Info
Excerpt

Excerpt from The Question of Peace in Modern Political Thought edited by Toivo Koivukoski and David Edward Tabachnick

From the Foreword by John Gittings

The voice of philosophy has a lot to say about peace, and in the present age we need to hear it more than ever. In a world that is globalized in its economy but still far from cosmopolitan in its outlook, the forces of prejudice, intolerance, and misunderstanding increase tension and generate conflict, both between and within nations. War, or the danger of war, exists at many levels—quite literally: on the ground, where ethnic and religious enmities spill over into violence, and in the upper atmosphere, where the cloud of nuclear war still hangs over us. Philosophers may not be the legislators of the world, but they can help us to clarify moral principles, understand reality, and distinguish true from false knowledge. That is what they are good at. The advice that past philosophers have offered on war and peace is still relevant today.

A group of these were the itinerant Chinese philosophers of the Hundred Schools of Thought, who would sit at the city gate of some small principality during the Era of Warring States (475—221 BC). Their role was to advise the ruler on strategy, such as whether or not to take advantage of a neighbouring state's weakness and invade. Most of the main Schools— the Confucians, the Mohists, and the Daoists (Taoists)—counselled against war, on both moral and practical grounds. Confucius's disciple Mengzi (Mencius) warned that wars to capture cities or territory always lead to disaster: they are a way of “teaching the earth how to eat human flesh. ” Mohists would cite Mozi (Mo Tzu) himself, who held that states should cooperate for their universal advantage: “If rulers love the states of others as their own, no one will commit aggression. ” A Daoist might quote his Master Laozi (Lao Tzu): “The ideal relationship between states is one in which they are so close that they can hear their neighbour's chickens squawk and dogs bark, and yet they leave each other alone. ” All these philosophers would urge rulers not be seduced by the rival school of Strategists, who claimed to know the secret of victory.

From Chapter 1: By the Grace of God: Peace and Martin Luther's Two Kingdoms by Jarrett A. Carty

The Reformation began in Germany with Martin Luther's protest against the sale of indulgences in 1517, and shortly expanded into a general schism within the Western church. Reform, Luther soon discovered, needed the cooperation of government, in which the civil authorities had a crucial role. Luther also needed theoretical justification for his Reformation, and guidance on its proper jurisdiction and limits. He looked for this guidance to the Bible and to the time of the apostles, believing that temporal government had once been independent of spiritual authority—and that the political tumult of his age was the result of spiritual authority having usurped government. True and lasting peace, he felt, could only come about through a proper respect for both of the distinct yet complementary “two kingdoms. “ The spiritual realm was ruled by Jesus Christ, through his Word; the secular realm was ruled by kings and civil authorities, through law and coercion. Its responsibilities were maintaining law and order, ensuring the protection of life and property, and promoting peace.

Luther held that wherever peace did not reign, and rebellion, war, or chaos, prevailed, the fault lay with the confusion of the two kingdoms— and the corruption of the spiritual by the temporal. The peace he sought, though, would prove to be tragically elusive. During his career, two major political controversies erupted: the Peasants' War of 1525, and the Protestant resistance against the Holy Roman Empire that began in 1530. And after his death in 1546, his views were challenged by the hardening of confessional church doctrines, and by the civil control of the churches in the wake of the Peace of Augsburg (1555).

close this panel
The Rivers North of the Future

The Rivers North of the Future

by David Cayley, foreword by Charles Taylor
edition:eBook
also available: Paperback
tagged : philosophy & social aspects, educators, political
More Info
X
Contacting facebook
Please wait...